EROS CORAZZA, WILLIAM FISH and JONATHAN GORVETT

نویسنده

  • EROS CORAZZA
چکیده

Whilst it may seem strange to ask to whom “I” refers, we show that there are occasions when it is not always obvious. In demonstrating this we challenge Kaplan’s assumption that the utterer, agent and referent of “I” are always the same person. We begin by presenting what we regard to be the received view about indexical reference popularized by David Kaplan in his influential 1972 “Demonstratives” before going on, in section 2, to discuss Sidelle’s answering machine paradox which may be thought to threaten this view, and his deferred utterance method of resolving this puzzle. In section 3 we introduce a novel version of the answering machine paradox which suggests that, in certain cases, Kaplan’s identification of utterer, agent and referent of “I” breaks down. In the fourth section we go on to consider a recent revision of Kaplan’s picture by Predelli which appeals to the intentions of the utterer, before arguing that this picture is committed to unacceptable consequences and, therefore, should be avoided if possible. Finally, in section 5, we present a new revision of Kaplan’s account which retains much of the spirit of his original proposal whilst offering a intuitively acceptable way to explain all of the apparently problematic data. In doing so, we also show how this picture is able to explain the scenario which motivated Predelli’s account without appealing to speaker intentions. 1. THE CLASSICAL VIEW First, some background. Pure indexicals, “I”, “here”, “now”, “today”, etc. have linguistic meanings, which are, roughly, conventions telling us how to use them. Its dictionary entry, for example, informs us that “I” stands for the speaker or writer. What the dictionary gives us aims to capture the linguistic rule governing its use. Hence a competent speaker knows, roughly, that “I” is the first person pronoun which stands for the utterer (or writer). Kaplan (1977), following Reichenbach (1947), in his logic of demonstratives argues that we should countenance a distinction between the Philosophical Studies 107: 1–21, 2002. © 2002 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands. 2 EROS CORAZZA ET AL. content of an indexical (its referent) and its character. The latter aims to capture the linguistic meaning of indexical expressions. On this account, the character of “I” is represented by a function that takes as argument the agent, and gives as value the referent. Kaplan argues that the logic of indexical terms forces the distinction between the utterer, the contextual parameters (agent, time, place and possible world) and the referents (contents). Kaplan argues that, as utterances are features of the world and hence occur in time, it is not possible to provide a semantic evaluation of utterances.1 To overcome this, we need instead to assess the abstract notion of a sentence-in-a-context, and to do this we need to endorse the notion of a context.2 The agent is, therefore, an essentially logical notion, a contextual parameter filling the argument of the character (qua function), and giving us the referent of the indexical, and, as such, is logically distinct from the notion of an utterer. However, Kaplan simply seems to assume that the utterer and the agent will always be identical and hence that the referent of “I” will always be the utterer. This account of indexical reference, therefore, appears to assume two identity statements; that the agent is the referent (from the character of “I”), and that the utterer is the agent.3 This account, therefore, can be represented in the following way: Determination of agent Determination of referent f = (The character of “I”) The utterer is the agent f: agent → referent While the utterer and referent are parts of the material world, the agent is a logical parameter, playing the role of taking us from the language to the world. When these two components are combined, we can see how Kaplan preserves the intuition that “I” refers to the speaker or writer. The agent-utterer identity ensures that, for every token of “I”, the contextual parameter of the agent is identified with the utterer, the individual who uses the token. The character of “I” then completes the task by returning the utterer (= the agent) as the referent of the token. The character of the other indexicals, “here” and “now”, can also be represented in the same way. In each case, the character of the

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

منابع مشابه

The dimensions of realization: a critique of the Standard view

Colterjohn, J. and D. MacIntosh. 1987. Gerald Vision and indexicals. Analysis 47: 58–60. Corazza, E., W. Fish, and J. Gorvett. 2002. Who is I? Philosophical Studies 107: 1–21. Everett, A. 2002. Predelli on procrastination. Analysis 62: 160–66. Kaplan, D. 1977. Demonstratives. Repr. in Themes From Kaplan, ed. J. Almog, J. Perry and H. Wettstein. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986. Predelli, S...

متن کامل

Contexts, Biases, and Reflexivity

In a recent, welcome contribution, Predelli (2013) presents a fruitful and powerful framework on how truth-conditional semantics can deal with non-truth-conditional meaning. One of the gifts of Predelli’s contribution is that it presents a unifying theory dealing with seemingly various phenomena often relegated to the pragmatics dustbin. Thus, nicknames, slurs, answering machines/post-its, voca...

متن کامل

Indexicals, Fictions, and Ficta

We defend the view that an indexical uttered by an actor works on the model of deferred reference. If it defers to a character which does not exist, it is an empty term, just as ‘Hamlet’ and ‘Ophelia’ are. The utterance in which it appears does not express a proposition and thus lacks a truth value. We advocate an ontologically parsimonious, anti-realist, position. We show how the notion of tru...

متن کامل

Sense and Insensibility Or Where Minimalism Meets Contextualism

As we understand it, semantic minimalism is the view that: (i) an utterance u of a (declarative) sentence S expresses a proposition p whose constituents must all be represented by elements of S; (ii) the structure of p reflects the logical form of S,1 and (iii) if S does not contain indexical expressions, u expresses p in a FN:1 context-independent way. This last claim can be illustrated in con...

متن کامل

Consistency Management in the EROS Kernel

EROS is a persistent operating system targeted towards managing resources with great longevity. The system provides a persistent single level store supporting two fundamental object types: nodes and pages. All primary objects, including memory segments and protection domains, are constructed out of these fundamental objects, and inherit their persistence. EROS is a pure capability system: acces...

متن کامل

ذخیره در منابع من


  با ذخیره ی این منبع در منابع من، دسترسی به آن را برای استفاده های بعدی آسان تر کنید

برای دانلود متن کامل این مقاله و بیش از 32 میلیون مقاله دیگر ابتدا ثبت نام کنید

ثبت نام

اگر عضو سایت هستید لطفا وارد حساب کاربری خود شوید

عنوان ژورنال:

دوره   شماره 

صفحات  -

تاریخ انتشار 2001